Showing posts with label international relations theory. Show all posts
Showing posts with label international relations theory. Show all posts

22.10.07

Think before you say - A Guide to using the Concept of 'Globalisation'





“Globalisation” was the Zeitgeist of the 1990s. In the social sciences, it gave rise to the claim that deepening interconnectedness was fundamentally transforming the nature of human society, and was replacing the sovereign state system with a multilayered, multilateral system of ‘global governance’. A decade later, however, these expectations appear already falsified by the course of world affairs.” (Rosenberg, 2005:3)

“As the counter-critique below indicates, scholars have imminently defensible grounds for persisting analyses of globalisation into the 21st century.” (Scholte, 2005:391)

A critical investigation of the competing scholarly claims relating to the concept of “globalisation”.

Index
INTRODUCTION
THEORETICAL GOAL POSTS
JUSTIN ROSENBERG – THE IMPORTANCE OF EXPLANATORY POWER
JAN AART SCHOLTE – A SMALLER WORLD IS A DIFFERENT WORLD
JOHN HOBSON – THE PROBLEM OF ORIENTALISM
ALEX CALLINICOS – CLAIMING ROOM FOR AN INTERMEDIATE ANALYSIS
ANDREW GAMBLE – WHY NOT CHERISH WELL-INTENTIONED GLOBALISATION THEORY?
GEORGE LAWSON – THE IMPORTANCE OF AGENCY
TESTING THE THEORY - GLOBALISATION THROUGH THE EYES OF CHINA
THE CASE OF CHINESE ENGAGEMENT IN AFRICA AND ITS LIGHT ON THE MANY GLOBALISATIONS
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES




Introduction

Before introducing the map of this essay I want to clarify that, in the lines of Justin Rosenberg, I understand globalisation as lacking considerable explanatory ability. However, I still consider it a useful term as long as those studying global political economy are aware of its shortcomings and use it within the correct descriptive properties it holds. The debate dissected here comprises of one long discussion surrounding the conceptualization of one single word. Recognized by Scholte in his 2002 paper, globalisation is usually used interchangeably with a multitude of other concepts such as: internationalization, liberalization, universalization and westernization.
First and foremost it is important to distinguish between ‘theories of globalisation’ of which there are many and ‘globalisation theories’ of which there is a handful. Globalisation theory was a term ‘coined’ by Rosenberg to put into evidence the academic “trap” that hyperglobalists fall into when believing that we have now moved beyond the state-centred Westphalian model and entered a new stage in the history of international relations. Globalisation theories in turn, allude to a multiplicity of understandings of globalisation ranging from: the debates over what the effects of a supposed globalisation are – homogeneity versus heterogeneity; to anti-globalisation theories such as those advanced by Brecher et al (2000) and Starr (2001); to the question if globalisation is actually secondary to a reigning form of Empire (Pieterse 2004).
One of the most interesting of these debates saw ‘homogeneizers’ and ‘heterogeneizers’ clash in a sort of post modern prediction of the evolution of cultural relations. Some authors proposing globalisation as a causal factor of hybridity such, as Held (1995) and his cosmopolitan theories, disagreed with heterogeneizers that refuted any linkage between an acceleration in economic integration and a trend towards cultural homogeneity.
However, in my critical discussion of the claims over the concept of globalisation I will go beyond these previous debates and focus instead on the reactions triggered by Justin Rosenberg’s treatment of the concept as a “folly”. This mention led Jan Scholte and other academics interested in the topic to embark upon a deep and sophisticated conceptual debate over the term. The ‘voyage’ will allow a better understanding of the academic disagreements over the use of the concept of globalisation and shed light on the positions of, not all, but a good selection of the most prominent scholars in the field. I will finalise by testing their main arguments against the challenging backdrop of China’s rise into prominence in international relations and what it can mean for globalisation theory.
After being immersed by the reading of the debate that follows I opted for an understanding that sees globalisation as consisting of: the acceleration in the accumulation of capital, which does not imply a full-blown systemic change in the political organization of accumulation, but does bring about more superficial yet versatile innovations in the modalities of accumulation, economic integration and socio-cultural interaction. Let us now take a look at how I got to this final conceptualisation.

Theoretical goal posts

Held, Macgrew, Goldblatt and Perraton (1999) introduced their piece “Global Transformations” with the statement that “globalisation” has become the “cliché of our times”. Held and Macgrew, criticized by Rosenberg (2005:4) as being part of the globalisation theory group, have nonetheless put forward a very useful and parsimonious typology framing the important ongoing debate. Given this, in order to make sure that this present reflection does not lose itself in the “sea” of literature on globalisation, I will be using as a framework the academic typologies put forward by Held et al that “box” theorists of globalisation into three different types: hyperglobalists; sceptics; and transformationalists. These three accounts will be the flag posts of my analysis. I will put forward a series of interpretations of globalisation from different prominent authors and localise them within the typologies. Then, I will try and expose their main strengths, difficulties and interrelations in their arguments and finalise by reflecting on how successfully their competing scholarly claims deal with the rise of China in a seemingly globalised world. China’s unprecedented growth and the massive challenges it faces will be used as a case-study to test and apply Global Political Economy globalisation theory.
In very simple terms, hyperglobalists are those that defend that the vortex of interconnectedness brought about by globalisation has fundamentally changed the organization of international relations and announced the death of the nation-state as we knew it. States have no choice but to become ‘decision takers” instead of “decision-makers”.
Sceptics argue the exact opposite, arguing that the current turn of events has only provided nation-states with further tools to advance their “grip” on the international system. The unit of the state is seen as invariably resilient and actually strengthened in the context of a globalised world.
The last typology is the most nuanced one. Transformationalists essentially look at globalisation as a great uncertainty. As a phenomenon which is perhaps not absolutely new, but that is now changing the basic state centric “rituals” of international relations. The main difference between transformationalists and the other two accounts of globalisation is that they have concluded what the end-product of the current era is going to be and on what exactly the future holds for the unit of the state. They argue that it is still an open and uncertain “game” whose outcome will necessarily be path dependent.

Justin Rosenberg – The importance of explanatory power

“Post-mortem: Globalisation Theory, deceased circa 2000. Cause of death: congenital misplaced concreteness, leading to terminal intellectual complications, compounded by sudden loss of life-supporting ideological plausibility.”
Justin Rosenberg’s post mortem of Globalisation theory (2005:65)

Justin Rosenberg is a sceptic by excellence. He fundamentally criticizes a group he labels as ‘globalisation theorists’ for erroneously identifying causality between the sets of processes encapsulated in the term globalisation and the supposedly fundamental transformations these processes are responsible for in the social world.
More strikingly, he goes to the point of claiming that “the actual historical movement which was called ‘globalisation’ is already in the past” (Rosenberg 2005:6). The idea of globalisation is criticized for not being able to explain any of the actual changes we are witnessing with success.
The question remains. How definitive is the passing of the globalisation zeitgeist that Justin Rosenberg so firmly announces? Rosenberg’s international historical sociological narrative is compelling, the alternative he presents fresh and provocative. This narrative comprises a conjunctural form of analysis that firmly believes that the “geographical scope of capitalism has been trans-societal from the start” (Rosenberg 2005:37), meaning that Globalisation Theorists are commemorating something ancient and “dusty” as being something new and unprecedented. The origins of the reigning model of state-supervised market economy as the model of organisation are everything but new. Adapting the words of Thomas Friedman (2005), the world has actually been “flat” for quite a while. More than realising that the world is ‘flat’ it is important to know why it became ‘flat’ in the first place. To put it simply, Rosenberg defends that the true role of global political economy is to look at the quantity and not the quality of the “flatness”. He argues that globalisation as a concept performs wonderfully with quantity and desperately struggles with quality.
His critique of hyperglobalists goes further, condemning them for not questioning the apparent “unilinear path of endogenous development” they put forward and for relying on spatio-temporal analyses that disregard the social sources of power (Rosenberg 2005: 9, 14). This critique is particularly targeting those seen as the more traditional hyperglobalist writers such as Friedman (2005), Emannuel Castells (1996) and Anthony Giddens (1999). In his seminal piece, “Globalisation Theory: a Post Mortem”, Rosenberg (2005:41) says that the current period/conjuncture should actually be analysed as being part of a wider and more ancient process of “uneven and combined development” On one of this best passages, Rosenberg recognizes that the volume of capital accumulation today is indeed impressive but questions if these have actually been the result of a deep “system-change” (Rosenberg 2005:26). He concludes his argument by dropping the provocative question: is globalisation not simply another word for interdependence?
In his last saying on the matter, an article that came out on September 2007 in the journal Globalisation, Rosenberg is at his best in eloquence and analytical parsimony. He puts forward a very strong argument that globalisation as a concept has little explanatory power. It is not a force that by itself drives anything or is directly responsible for integrating societies in new ways; hybridising world cultures; spreading industrialisation; extending the influence of the European Union, and making international organisations proliferate (Rosenberg 2007:420). Globalisation is ultimately portrayed as being insipid in its attempt at social scientific explanation.

Jan Aart Scholte – A smaller world is a different world

From an alternative transformationalist perspective, Jan Aart Scholte (1999:18) departed from a critique of the social sciences as being traditionally too pinned down to “methodological territorialism”. The persistence of this type of methodology meant that scholars were badly equipped to fully understand the extension of the transformations occurring when the process of globalisation came “knocking at their door”. The transformationalist critique of Rosenberg, put forward by Scholte, is in my opinion the strongest and most pervasive. His current understanding of the scene of Global Political Economy as being underpinned by an inherent “polycentrism” is sound and analytically useful. Polycentrism refers to the apparent particularity of multi-layered and diffused governance of the present era (2004, 2005b).
I too agree that Rosenberg slightly overstretched his argument against the historical novelty of globalisation when he argues that “the actual historical movement which was called globalisation is already in the past” (Rosenberg 2005:6). Rosenberg does commit the fallacy of bundling together moderate transformationalist theorists of globalisation with theorists that have been describing since the 1990s an era of hyperglobalisation. An era that is seemingly here and now, ready-made, presented to us on a tray of magical special compression and technological evolution.
Rosenberg had argued that Scholte’s work was over-focused on changes at the levels of spatiality. Scholte’s response is that he does not see why is it not “possible to argue that space matters without going to a ‘spacist’ extreme” (2005:394). This response is sensible. His point is essentially that, when designing a theory of globalisation in Global Political Economy, a certain degree of uncertainty and hesitation on what concerns the future does not reflect weakness per se. As Scholte puts it, the result of “multidimensional systemic causation (…) need not to be ‘directionless indeterminacy’ (2005:395). Scholte’s final and most compelling point is that Rosenberg does not tackle the “nitty gritty” of the current process of globalisation, failing to look at the “changing forms of commodification within contemporary capitalism” and the advent of “communications capital, consumer capital, finance capital, genetic capital, information capital, and the atomic capital of emergent nanotechnology” (Scholte 2005:398). This is a very good point, capitalism even if recognized as a mode of production whose social relations can be traced back to a much ancient long duree, is indeed changing dramatically.
Rosenberg returns to the debate by claiming that all he is criticizing hyperglobalists for is for using the term globalisation as one that goes beyond mere description. He refutes the implicit notion that we now live in a systemically different system where there has been a major breakthrough in the economic and social relations of global political economy. Globalisation as advanced by hyperglobalists is once again cast as a fading hype lacking explanatory edge.
John Hobson – The problem of orientalism

A question that may be asked of Rosenberg’s seminal work is that if his understanding manages to escape outside John Hobson’s critique of Orientalism. John Hobson puts forward a Edward Said-inspired assertion that Justin Rosenberg’s Marxist-inspired work is Eurocentric and constructed in a “line of civilization-apartheid” (2005:374).
Rosenberg recognises his Eurocentrism to some degree but defends his primary focus on the long duree by recalling the idea that the concept of globalisation per se is empty and not analytical enough since it does not recognize the uneveness of relations between societies that goes back at least to the middle of the 19th century. (Rosenberg 2007:461).

Alex Callinicos – Claiming room for an intermediate analysis

Alex Callinicos (2005), also a sceptic of globalisation theory, agrees first and foremost with Rosenberg when it comes to the understanding of the economic integration witnessed throughout the 1990s as simply not being historically unprecedented. It is, in fact, part of a much greater and longer duree a la Fernand Braudel (1982), part of an “historical conjuncture” which needs to be analysed from a few centuries ago onwards, in order to be properly understood. In his piece, “Epoch and Conjuncture” Callinicos celebrates Rosenberg’s historicism. Reminding readers how the “euphoric proclamations of Globalisation theory” (2005:361) were a product of the 1981-1991 rupture with the Cold War. After his celebration however, Callinicos argues that the type of conjunctural analysis that Rosenberg proposes should not substitute a conceptualisation that includes general theory in a way that is able to distinguish between “two kinds of intermediary analysis (…) – epoch and conjuncture ” (2005:42). In a nutshell, a differentiation and a simultaneous combination of the two dimensions can be a much more useful analytical tool for scholars studying the peculiarities of globalisation. This may be particularly be the case, as we shall see, when it comes to generating better understandings of exceptional accumulation processes, both in form and in proportion, by state actors such as China.
Rosenberg defends his argument by reminding Callinicos that the “international” does not penetrate enough in such a conception of capitalist development” (Rosenberg 2007:478). He also alludes to the idea that “capitalist exchange relations have always been implicitly ‘supra-territorial’” (Rosenberg 2007:466), strengthening the point that scholars should use the long historical duree as the starting point for analysing the conditions of global political economy.

Andrew Gamble – Why not cherish well-intentioned globalisation theory?

Justin Rosenberg’s argument on globalisation has meanwhile been taken by Andrew Gamble (2005:367), simplified and commented upon in very constructive ways. Gamble puts forward what is a clear transformationalist argument. He agrees with Rosenberg on his qualification of globalisation theory as over-descriptive and with his reminder of the old Marxist adage that the capitalist system “was both domestic and international from its very beginning”. Rosenberg’s elaborations on the differences between Hegemony and Empire are also recognized as analytically useful and Rosenberg is further supported on the defence that capitalism cannot exist without the modern state, that sovereign states are required to provide the conditions for the accumulation of capital.
The crux of Gamble’s critique lies with Rosenberg’s quick dismissal of globalisation theorists benign “normative hopes (…) that the structure of collective hegemony, which is now in place, is far deeper and more extensive than that which existed in the 19th century”. What clearly gives away Gamble as a transformationalist is his conclusion that the game is open and that “the test will be the rise of India and China during the next few decades to be leading players in the global economy” (Gamble 2005:371). This is precisely the discussion to which I will turn in the last section.
Once again, Rosenberg replies by saying that Andrew Gamble forgot that what he disputes is not a change in the nuances of the relation between sovereignty and the world market argument, but that he finds it much important to understand “the overall character of the process” (Rosenberg 2007:471). He goes further to quote Linda Weiss (1999, 59) and, although he incurres once again in the problematic generalization of putting hyperglobalists and transformationalists in the same bag, remember that “the dispute between globalists and sceptics is not about the reality of change but about the nature and significance of the changes under way as well as the driving forces behind them”.

George Lawson – The importance of agency

Lawson is also a transformationalist with a particular focus on the importance of agency. He starts out his argument by contrasting his position with what he perceives to be Rosenberg’s reductionism and focus on “easy-targets” (2005:382). George Lawson’s main point is very simple. He claims that, without discarding the importance of looking at long historical waves and the relational social structures they put in place, one must also take into account the substantial role that specific actors can occasionally have in influencing the very system of historical conjunctural relations. Only then can one avoid reductionism when criticizing globalisation theory.

Testing the theory - Globalisation through the eyes of China

“China is a rotting semicivilization…vegetating in the teeth of time”
Karl Marx 1848-1862 (in Avinieri 1969:343)

In the latest engagements with the continent a fascinating phenomenon has come to about. The success in the accumulation of capital by China in the last couple of years has been absolutely tremendous, as Callinicos (2005:362) puts it “where would the world economy be today without the prodigious accumulation process under way in China, a process that is made possible by a very tight set of linkages between the state, the banking system, and both publicly and privately owned firms?”
Most strikingly, the heterogeneity in the modes of accumulating capital is becoming more notorious, particularly in the distinctiveness of equally productive and functional capitalist outputs by intrinsically diverse socio-political organizations of the state. I am thinking of the current ascendancy of China and India in the architecture of International Political Economy whose growth rates and competitiveness are telling, but that could not be more apart in terms of political system and the current social sources of power. India is a federalized decentralized system characterized by the prominence of centripetal forces while China presents a much more centralized and State controlled economic model. Both seem to be doing reasonably well in adapting to the international capitalist mode of production, probably in an unprecedented scale.
An interesting question to be posed in the debate over globalisation therefore is how it affects the sovereign state system and if there are indeed any alternatives to the invariable erosion of the state put forward by hyperglobalists. At a first glance, as we saw, China is an example of how trends announced by hyperglobalists are, to a great extent, not coming about.
China as a case study both confirms and challenges Rosenberg’s theory. On the one hand the sovereignty and the centralism of the state apparatus, despite some incoming challenges, remain reified and has began to operate according to modern pushes towards state accumulation of capital.
On the other hand, the form of this astonishing growth, despite having its origins at least all the way back Deng Xiaoping’s open door policy that started in 1978, has assumed breathtaking proportions in the last ten to fifteen years. Again, this means nothing per se. Nonetheless, the potential influence of China’s rise in the current conjuncture of capitalist accumulation which Rosenberg traces all the way back to at least the 18th century[1] remains uncertain.
Rosenberg’s questioning of understandings of political economy that accept a unilinear path of growth is very strong and is, I believe, one of the major problems with some of the writings of so-called ‘globalisation theorists’. However, I cannot help but recognize that, since the beginning of the 1990s, China has indeed witnessed growth of such a nature that it has, together with India, been pushing aggregated world growth in that direction. Most remarkably, although not without great challenges, on its way up China has pulled millions above the poverty line and was somehow left unscathed by successive financial crises in Latin America (1998, 1999), the United States (2000, 2007) and even in its own region (1997). The date limit and sustainability of this growth remains the “million renminbi question” of the next few decades.
The case of China also shows that, although at root capital accumulation remains the same, today the process goes beyond the simple schema of an interstate system replicating uneven power relations that divide those holding the means of production and those who do not. Indeed, China now presents remarkable new forms of innovation. The Chinese model is set to profoundly challenge, maybe not the economic system as Rosenberg understands it, but most definitely the international economic equilibrium. It is set to do so by among other means, putting its 800 million labour force and 1.3 billion consumers to use. China is also set to revolutionise cost innovation by already starting to market: high technology at low cost; greater choice of products; and speciality products at lower prices (Zeng & Williamson 2007). The material processes “flattening” spatiality such as the onset of international supply chains, the phenomena of outsourcing and the acceleration in the opening of markets, have all contributed to this, as was recognized by Scholte (2005). Again, all of these changes do not necessarily imply a new age in the relations of political economy. It can always be understood as the latest stage of an old political process that endures and that continues to have state-supervised market economy as the model of organisation.
Hobson’s (2005) point, alluding to Rosenberg’s orientalism, brings to mind broad questions such as if China has been writing its own history, particularly after the period of the Opium Wars. Looking at Chinese recent history it is clear that the country’s isolationist tendencies have been drastically challenged. China has indeed been fairly reactive when it comes to the evolution of international relations ever since it was militarily forced by Britain to “smoke the opium” in 1839. This reactive role however does not mean that China has been having or will have a passive role in setting and influencing the evolution of the long duree. It was a key player in the Cold War, particularly in what was happening in some parts of Africa and cunningly balanced its relation with the two super-powers. Also, in the present era, China is slowly and perhaps informally starting to challenge the traditional five principles of its international relations[2] (Kornberg & Faust 2005:14). It is doing so in a new approach and involvement in South-South cooperation and its business abroad where its interactions with economic, diplomatic, social and security issues are becoming more and more complex. My point is that China is starting to realise it will have no choice but to have a much more proactive role in its international relations and this means it will probably be at the forefront of affecting the design of the next socio-political long duree.
Finally, to pay a bit of lip-service to George Lawson (2005), looking at agency through the eyes of China for the purposes of this reflection is a tricky affair. On the one hand the roles of actors such as Deng Xiao Ping in pushing through with the open door policy or, more recently, Hu Jintao significant criticism of his own party (Times Online 2007) cannot be underestimated. Likewise, events such as the incoming Beijing Olympics can bring about unforeseen structural changes. However, I have to agree with Rosenberg and ask at what level these changes can actually be meaningful. In this sense, it would not be the case that an unexpected, dramatic quick shift towards multi-party democracy led by Hu Jintao or triggered by the 2008 Olympics would not affect countries and peoples elsewhere. The important question is if the scope of the events set in motion by this one man or event would ever have the potential to suddenly alter the fundamental premises of the international model of capital accumulation. Probably not, as Justin Rosenberg and Fernand Braudel show us ever so well, these vaster structural changes have traditionally tended to take a while and be more ‘tectonic’ in nature.
[1] I would actually trace back to the 15th/16th century age of the discoveries but for obvious reasons of length I will not be discussing this argument further.
[2] The five principles are: mutual respect for sovereignty; nonaggression;noninterference in each other’s internal affairs; equality and mutual benefit; and peaceful coexistence
The case of Chinese engagement in Africa and its light on the many Globalisations

In its engagement with Africa for example, China is at times challenging the sovereignty and the traditional moulds of inter-state relations and sometimes cementing it. The challenge to sovereignty is present when we see China focusing its engagement with private companies or particular stakeholders within particular regions which are in turn within sovereign states. This is the case for example with the Niger Delta areas and the private oil companies operating in Nigeria as well as with the oil-rich area of Southern Sudan. It is possible that the added importance that China’s engagement brings to these actors and sub-state geographical units is not system-changing. It does however give “food for thought” on how to understand the unit of the state, international relations and most importantly the meaning of today’s acceleration in capital accumulation for Africa.
As a rule of thumb, the public and the “corporate” private sector tend to be one and the same in the African state given the tendency for the appropriation of the state by patrimonial networks of patronage (Chabal & Daloz 1999). This has, among other reasons, encouraged the Chinese to prefer high level diplomacy to set up their aid, trade and investment. This kind of engagement tends to reify the sovereignty and the political leverage of patrons in the state apparatus. The use of the state as an instrument for the accumulation of wealth is particularly prominent in some African states causing top private sector companies of the countries to lack efficiency and the will to seek markets and expand. This connection to the international global economy puts into evidence what is a drastically different interaction of regions and states with the current accelerated processes of capital accumulation. One of the reasons why there is very little private sector investment from Africa in China and abroad is therefore because the few rent-seeking patrons controlling the state are extremely intimate with the big nationalized sectors and the companies have no incentives or capacity to tap into the broader international supply-chains of the international economy.
This goes to show how ultimately, in the context of global political economy, the use of the concept of globalisation does not explain the great differences in opportunities and challenges that a country such as Swaziland faces in comparison with, for example, China. Justin Rosenberg also does not directly answer this question but does recognise globalization theorists’ failure to do so. As a concept, globalisation is better at describing the pace of economic growth and change than at understanding the “political” in the political economy of international relations. Conceptually, it struggles with the origins, distribution and the forms of maintenance of the current modes of economic organization and it has difficulties in shedding any light on the concrete sources of social power.


Conclusion


The debate of how “new” and “recent” the current set of relations of Global Political Economy is, has been slowly progressing in the past few years and nothing has been more fascinating than the abundant and thorough academic discussion triggered by Justin Rosenberg’s provocative piece – “Globalisation Theory – a post mortem”. Although rife with some instances of theoretical caricaturing and misinterpretation, the debate has streamlined the quality of the arguments of different schools of thought and improved the thoroughness of their theoretical beliefs. All of those who study political economy should be aware of the ‘heated’ debate around the term and of what it means to how we understand the complexity of the current era. That will allow us to better understand the highly visible changes the world has been through but also, and most importantly, allow us to challenge these processes and understand how significant and historically revolutionary they actually are.
For that reason, and drawing from the debate, globalisation must be approached carefully. It holds little explanatory ability but the job it does at describing and situating the new forms of capital accumulation should also be acknowledged as important. It should not be treated as historically unprecedented and its difficulty in analysing the nuances in the origins of social and political power should be both urgently acknowledged and urgently addressed.
To conclude, after all this debate, I propose a more textured conceptualization of globalisation as referring to: an acceleration in the accumulation of capital, which does not imply a full-blown systemic change in the political organization of accumulation, but does bring about more superficial yet versatile innovations in the modalities of accumulation, economic integration and socio-cultural interaction.

References

Avinieri, S. 1969 Karl Marx on Colonialism and Modernization New York: Anchor
Braudel, F. 1982 On History The University of Chicago Press
Brecher et al 2000 Globalisation from Below: The power of solidarity South End Press
Callinicos, A. 2005 “Epoch and Conjuncture in Marxist Political Economy” international Politics No.42
Castells, E. 1996 The Rise of the Network Society, Oxford: Blackwell
Chabal, P. & Daloz, J 1999 Africa Works: The Political Instrumentalization of Disorder - Indiana University Press
Friedman, T. 2005 The World is Flat New York: Farrar
Gamble, A. 2005 “Globalization: Getting the ‘Big Picture’ Right, A comment on Justin Rosenberg” International Politics No.42
Giddens, A. 1999 Runaway world London: Profile Books
Held, D. 1995 Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance, Cambridge: Polity
Held, D. et al. 1999 “Global Transformations” The global transformations Website http://www.polity.co.uk/global/whatisglobalization.asp?style=print [19 October 2007]
Hobson, J. 2005 “Deconstructing Rosenberg’s ‘Contribution to the Critique of Global Political Economy’, A (re)view from a non-Eurocentric bridge of the world” International Politics No.42
Kornberg, J. & Faust, J. 2005 China in World Politics London: Lynne Rienner
Lawson, G. 2005 “Rosenberg’s Ode to Bauer, Kinkel and Willich” International Politics No. 42 Palgrave
Pieterse, J. 2004 Globalisation or Empire London: Routledge
Rosenberg, J. 2005 “Globalization Theory: A Post Mortem” International Politics No.42 Palgrave
Rosenberg, J. 2007 “International Relations – The ‘Higher Bullshit’: A Reply to the Globalisation Theory Debate International Politics No 44 Palgrave
Scholte, J. 1999 “Globalisation: Prospects for a Paradigm Shift”, in M. Shaw (ed.) Politics and globalisation, London: Routledge
Sholte, J. 2002 “What is globalisation? The definitional issue – again” CSGR Working Paper No. 109/02 CSGR: University of Warwick
Scholte, J. 2004 “Globalisation and Governance: from Statism to Polycentrism” CSGR Working Paper, University of Warwick
Scholte, J. 2005 “Premature Obituaries: A response to Justin Rosenberg” Review of International Politics No. 42
Scholte, J. 2005 b Globalisation: A Critical Introduction, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan
Starr, A. 2001 Naming the Enemy: Anti-Corporate Movements confront Globalisation Zed Books
Times Online 2007 “Hu Jintao pledges to tackle wealth gap and corruption in China” http://www.timesonline.co.uk/tol/news/world/asia/article2661790.ece [22 October 2007]
Weiss, L. 1999 “Globalisation and National Governance: Antimony or Interdependence? Review of International Studies. No 25 (Special issue)
Zeng, M. & Williamson, P. 2007 Dragons at your door Boston: Harvard Business School Press

28.5.07

What good is International Relations Theory for the developing world?


“…the claimed inappropriateness of traditional IR to the African experience thus reinforces the marginalisation of the continent in the international system with a marginalisation within the discipline” (Brown 2006:219)


A critical discussion of this view, also shedding light on the more general question of how our understanding of international relations is subverted (or enriched) by the dominant discourse of the American scholarship?

Introduction

Brown’s comment comes about in the context of an emerging body of literature that recognises and questions the consequences of a discipline of International Relations that was created in the West and during a time in which most of the world was colonized by Western powers.

This means that, in a way, much of the body of literature does not only reflect a Western or European cultural heritage but also a worldview which once justified the colonization of non-Western peoples. Just like in the case of Feminism, it was initially expected that the political emancipation – decolonization – would put to an end the inequalities between the Western and the non-Western world. Yet, this hope has proven wrong.

Post-colonialist theory, a category in which Brown’s comment and text falls into, thus theorizes the continuing inequalities and the means by which they are reproduced. Prominent amongst these means is the construction of knowledge which excludes the particular experiences, issues, and contributions of non-European peoples to international history and politics. In its critique, post-colonialism does not just address the orthodoxy of International Relations but also the so-called critical approaches by arguing that non-Western people are facing the triple oppression of race, class and gender.

Brown’s critique primarily targets Neo-realism. He believes that, because it is the most mainstream of International Relations approaches, an analysis and critique of its underpinning beliefs can effectively demonstrate how the African continent has been neglected from the central debates of the discipline.

A quick analysis of the chronology of International Relations as a discipline shows how it has to a large extent been an Anglo-Saxon affair. All of International Relations’ big debates have originated and been dominated by authors with headquarters and origins somewhere in the West and most probably in Britain, the United States or Canada. This constitutes a fascinating debate because, despite sound criticism over this situation, the tendency for a globalisation of the discipline in terms of overture for alternative non-Western approaches in general and African approaches in particular has been severely questioned by authors such as Brown.





The historical legacies of the enlightenment and the sheer amount of investment poured into education, research and development in the West does go a long way in explaining, though not fully justifying. Socrates, Plato, Descartes, Leibniz and Kant were some of the forefathers of Western essentialism and served as the basis for an hegemony in the social sciences that has been characterized by reductionism, Eurocentrism and over-generalizations (Atabaki 2002:7). This essentialism found its way into International Relations theory for example in the scientific aspirations of Neo-Realism. Although it is an ongoing discussion within epistemology and the philosophy of knowledge, one can consider that the prominence of this essentialism, understood as the belief that it is at least theoretically possible to attribute set and universal characteristics to an entity, is one of the central problems of what is being debated. Mainstream theory from the West and its universalistic, one-size-fits-it-all approaches are primarily criticized on these terms.

The direction of knowledge and of research in the sciences is of a normative nature, though not necessarily of a consciously hegemonic one. In this sense, the very hiatus in the economic division of labour at the global level and the imbalances between North and South constitute a continuation of persistent patterns of control and subjugation that originated during the colonial period. This is where the term “post-colonial” term for some niches of International Relations theory arises, one that works both as an attempt to put the unfairness of these continuities under the spotlight but also one that offers a normative alternative to theory-making that replicates the status-quo. The fact of the matter is that the Westphalian Eurocentric state model ended up being exported and internationally recognized as the primary form of political organization. Though the state-centrism of the international order is undoubtedly being challenged, state sovereignty remains a crucial premise of international relations meaning that literature can sometimes be harshly accused of using a Eurocentric template for their analysis as this template has, to some extent, gained a “life of its own” and has been consistently used as a point of departure for all other alternative approaches in International Relations. This “life of its own” however can still be rightly criticized as simply consisting in the reification of historically specific social forms, in this case statism and anarchy, which reduce the study of international relations to timeless struggles of power of static uni-dimensional actors (Rosenberg 1994).

The African example is illustrative of these tensions, though frequently the political systems in place hardly resemble fully fledged sovereign state machine. Even if you recognise the label of “failed state”, meaning a weak state whose central government has difficulties in having practical control over its whole territory (Thurer 1999), as being potentially problematic, states that face these control problems at different levels are still legally and politically recognized as sovereign. This means that even if a realist approach can, for example, shed no light in the internal political affairs of the state and tell us very little about the reasons for its foreign policy, it can shed some light on why other fellow sovereign states behave towards that specific political unit the way they do.

Moreover, these paradoxes have not been fully ignored and have actually increasingly come to the forebear in Western writings as can be noticed in the work of Boas, Herbst and Eriksen (2003;2004;2005). The West is slowly coming to terms with the huge pressure that ongoing geopolitical fragmentation has exercised on an international system whose foundations rest upon a state-based template is particularly interesting. This western nation-state template worked at its best when it dealt strictly with formal sovereign states but has since been struggling, particularly in Africa, where it has to deal with weak states managed by ‘muscled’ regimes and by the recurrence of protracted conflict. In his insightful work, Herbst (2004:308) notes that there has not been a process of natural selection in terms of state capabilities in Africa since the “political existence of states was no longer necessarily threatened by failure”. Indeed what has occurred instead seems to have been, in my perspective, a process of natural selection of which regimes hold power to the artificially colonially created state templates.

It is slowly being recognized that the criteria for a ‘muscled’ regime is different of the criteria for a strong state. It is here where the problem of the accusation of state-centrism on Western writings lies. An analysis that has as the state unit its departing point but that is not necessarily state-centric remains useful since failed states tend to hold regimes whereby the first decisive factor for natural selection is military capability and secondly, when in power, ability to keep in place a patrimonial structure that makes the most of an informal underground sector or/and an unaccountable primary commodity export sector (Liberia from Tubman to Charles Taylor is one example). All of this whilst, of course, managing to keep any forms of civil unrest on the low. On this instance, Eriksen for example, is quick in recognizing the essentially distinct new nature of conflict in Africa when he observes that states in themselves “are not faced with the threat of extinction (Eriksen: 2005: 1110). It is as if war does not destroy or make states (Tilly, 1985) as it used to. What you have now are direct battles between regimes, regime-seekers or stakeholder regime-establishers (like for example Angola and Libya in the Democratic Republic of Congo war) instead of simple inter-state battle. Herbst’s (2004 310) remark that “regimes do not require national political order” supports this, he pushes for an understanding of political order in terms of administrative accountability and control of the territorial extension of the state. These would be pre-requisites for states to be considered sovereign and would prevent regime-seekers from ripping out the benefits of belonging to the international community as soon as they control the capital city.

Although this understanding can be seen as once again hegemonic in its indirect conception of the orderly, centralized state as the best model, it represents nonetheless legitimate efforts to challenge the status quo and the inadequacies of traditional approaches of International Relations to analytically understand the specificities of the African models and as Brown puts it, at “exploring more developed theories of the state than realism has to offer” (Brown 2006:132). These are sets of theories that aim at avoiding situations whereby leaders and policy-makers in developing countries perceive an empowerment of the state as counter-productive to the strengthening of the regime. The hegemony of this discourse might still be open to debate but it is a discourse and an idea that has thoroughly permeated the masses of African citizens under both democratic and less democratic regimes.

Ultimately, Herbst’s (2004:312) suggestion for the international community to decertify states (not recognize them as sovereign) can surely strike us as ambiguous and impractical but one can also could see that it was a product both of logical reasoning exercise but also of a clear challenge to traditional forms of thinking in International Relations. In failed states there seems to be a parallel structure of neo-patrimonialism that uses the old state template of the international order as a platform for sustenance, a template that is more often that not replicated by the mainstream discourses of International Relations theory such as Neo-realism. Understanding traditional theories remains honest attempts at understanding how these regime-seeker factions tap into template that is discursive but also institutional. A template whereby the traditional rituals of state protocol and recognition have sometimes artificially given conflict entrepreneurs the ability to log into the international economy (formally or informally), log into transnational networks as well as given them the ability to remain to hold asymmetrical amounts of power as long as they seize strategic nodal points (instead of large extensions of territory) such as capital cities and river basins. These templates cannot just be disregarded as “neo-colonial” theory since they stand as insightful theories that digest the complexity of reality and translate it into more understandable schemes of thought. As Brown recognizes, not recognizing every single nitty-gritty actor, process and interaction in Africa is not the same as “missing the point” (2006: 124).

IR as Hegemony - Western domination and subversion of discourse

On a piece that mixes quantitative with qualitative data, Weaver (1998) sets out to understand the politics of publishing within the field of International Relations. He concludes that, besides European journals being understandably less American-dominated, the field in the United States is much more limited in terms of publishing and career opportunities for non-rational choice approaches than is the case in other Western non-American spheres.

In a seminar brief about the state of International Relations, Smith (2000) posed the question of the existence of an American Hegemony in the field. The findings corroborated Neuman’s critique of International Relations as being over-positivist and frequently having unfounded universalistic ambitions. Smith found that American International Relations in particular, when comparing for example with the case of the United Kingdom, for a large part privileged positivism. The direct comparison Smith puts together of the American and the British schools of International Relations also shows that the field does not consist of an uniform mass of thought and that it is actually constantly in a dynamic process of change and reinvention as there are pockets or research, namely that comprising reflectivist approaches, that are potentially better prepared for some of the new global challenges such as the illicit trade in diamonds, the overflow of illegal trade in small arms and light weapons, and the real nature of the processes behind Post Cold War “New Wars” than others (Smith 2000: 376).

In relation to how these technical differences apply in the theoretical approaches themselves, Neuman is quick to observe the hegemonic character of mainstream International Relations by pointing out to its universalistic ambitions (1998: 2). This can arguably represent a form of cultural chauvinism. Going back to Brown’s argument one can most definitely understand International Relations theory as being traditionally subject to a state-centric and positivist debate, particularly by the realist-liberal debate, one that is ancient and that despite some substantial transformations an innovation is still ongoing and dominant in the field. The most classical example of the critique of Westerm civilization’s discursive domination is the one advanced by Edward Said and his “Orientalism” thesis (Said 1978). He looks at the long historical trends and succession of events that put together a mythological archive and sets of identities that put the West and the East in positions of fundamental opposition. This opposition is not only cemented in the psyche of those on each side of the barriers but also replicated by means of social construction and representations that in this case can include writings in International Relations. The notion of socially replicated oppositions ties in nicely with Neuman’s argument that rational choice theories have presented IR with an Eurocentric approach in that the rational model, as abstract as it is, is in its inception crafted in Europe and excludes other non-Western rationales which are in an extreme case automatically taken as irrational. It can also to a certain extent explain the absence of Africa from International Relations theory that is concomitant to the perception of Africans as agency-lacking individuals when it comes to meaningful political matters as is noted by Dunn. This critique has almost “violent” repercussions on his view of the current state of affairs of International Relations theory in that oversimplification such as :Kaplan’s coming anarchy (2001) [then criticized as “new barbarism”(Tuastad 2003)];Huntington’s “Clash of Civilizations” (1993); and Fukuyama’s “End of history” (1992). These not only undermine the field of study but also have serious implication when it comes to the practical empirical sub-products of theory-building.

Conclusion

In conclusion, despite the fact that the West in general and the United States as functioned as historically been functioning as the “engine” of the discipline, this has not meant that the main bodies of literature have been fully impermeable. Mainstream theory-building, perhaps if not so receptive yet to alternative is at least slowly realizing thee fundamental changes that are occurring in its eclectic object of study to which strictly rationalist approach are less and less seen as enough. Also, if there is a Western discursive dominance in the field, this dominance is not so monochromatic as Dunn and Neuman portray it and is in fact, particularly in the United Kingdom, slowly coming to terms with the problematic of euro-centrism and orientalism.

This is dues to, among other reasons, the idea that traditional International Relations has to some extent struggled to fully understand and mechanize some of the problems that are top of the international agenda in the 21st century such as the changing nature of war and the issues of state-building in Africa. Why is it that because it is a government purchasing the weapons this is more likely to be seen as legal? This is particularly relevant in a world where it is now recognized that the nation-state as an entity is a shadow of what Westphalia proposed it to be, a world where borders are less resilient and where actors and challenges increasingly cut across them. Theories of failed states, state formation and decertification (Herbst: 2004) pop to mind and it could be interesting to analyse SALW through these perspectives. Reading Herbst and complementing the two texts, it is perhaps time to move from the classic argument that states make war and “war makes states” (Tilly, 1985:171) to a situation where regime-stakeholders make war and war both makes regimes and unravels states.

This means that traditional and alternative approaches to in the field need to build bridges in order to understand not only the breaks with the past and the particularities of the developing world but also the endurance and relevance of concepts such as interdependence, state-building and anarchy. These do play a role in the developing world in general and Africa in particular, at least as regions that are affected and incorporated in the wider sphere of the international system (Brown 2006:143). and its attached mainstream discourse.
References

Atabaki, T. 2002 Beyond Essentialism: Who Writes Whose Past in the Middle East and Central Asia?, Inaugural Lecture as Extraordinary Professor of the Social History of the Middle East and Central Asia in the University of Amsterdam
Boas, M. 2003. “Weak states, strong regimes: towards a ‘real’ political economy of African regionalization” in Grant, J. & Soderbaum, F. (eds) The New Regionalism in Africa. Aldershot: Ashgate
Brown, W. 2006 “Africa in international relations: a comment on IR theory, anarchy and statehood” in Review of International Studies, vol. 32, no.1
Carporaso, J. 1993 ‘International Relations theory and multilateralism: the search for foundations’ in J. Ruggie (ed.) Multilateralism Matters: The theory and Praxis of an Institutional Form New York: Columbia University Press
Chernoff, F. 2002 “Scientific Realism as a Meta-Theory of International Politics” International Studies Quarterly, vol.46, 198-207
Copeland, D. 1996 “Economic Interdependence and War” International Security, Vol. 20 No. 4
Dunn, K. 2001 “Introduction: Africa and International Relations Theory” in Kevin Dunn and Timothy Shaw (eds.) Africa’s challenge to International Relations Houndsmills: Palgrave
Eriksen, S. 2005. “The Congo war and the prospects for state formation: Rwanda and Uganda compared” in Third World Quarterly, 26(7)
Fukuyama, F. 1992 The End of History and the Last Man. Free Press
Grieco, J. 1990. Cooperation Among Nations: Europe, America, and Non-tariff Barriers to Trade. Ithaca: Cornell University Press
Guzzini, S. 2001 “The significance and the Roles of Teaching Theory in International Relations” Journal of International Relations and Development, Vol.4, No.2
Herbst, J. 2004. “Let them fail”, in Rotberg, R. (ed.) When states fail: Causes and Consequences. Princeton University Press
http://www.opendemocracy.net/conflict-iraq/wrong_war_2591.jsp (13 October 2006)
The Clash of Civilizations 1993 Foreign Affairs Summer 1993
Kaldor, M. 2001. New Wars and Old Wars: Organized Violence in a Global Era Oxford: Polity
Kaplan, R. 2001 “The coming anarchy: shattering the dreams of the Post Cold War” New York: Vintage
Katzenstein, P. 1976 “International Relations and Domestic Structures: Foreign Economic Policies of Advanced Industrial States” International Organisation Vol.30, No.1
Keohane, R. & Martin, L. 1994 “The promise of institutionalist theory (response to John. J. Mearsheimer,) International Security Vol.20 No.1
Keohane, R. (ed.) 1986 “Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond” in Neorealism and its critics New York: Columbia University Press
Krasner, S. 2001 “Rethinking the sovereign state model” Review of International Studies Vol. 27
Mearsheimer, J. 1994 “The false promise of International Institutions” International Security vol.19 no.3
Neuman, S. 1998 International Relations Theory and the Third World London: Macmillan
Nkiwane, C. T. 2001. “Africa and international relations: Regional lessons for a global siscourse. International Political Science Review. Vol. 22, No. 3, 279-290
Rosenberg, J. 1994 The Empire of Civil Society London: Verso
Ruggie, A. 1993 “Multilateralism: the anatomy of an institution,’ in J. G. Ruggie (ed.) Multilateralism Matters: The Theory and Praxis of an Institutional Form New York: Columbia University Press
Said, Edward W. 1978 Orientalism. New York: Pantheon Books
Simmons, B. & Elkins, Z. 2004 “The globalisation of Liberalisation: Policy diffusion in the International Political Economy” American Political Science Review Vol.98 Issue 171-189
Thurer, D. 1999 “The ‘failed State’ and international law” International Review of the Red Cross No. 836, p. 731-761
Tilly, C. 1985. “War Making and State Making as organised crime” in Evans, P.; Rueschemeyer, D. & Skocpol, T. (eds) Bringing the State back in Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
Tustad, D. 2003 “Neo-Orientalism and the new barbarism thesis: aspects of symbolic violence in the Middle Eastconflict(s)” Third World Quarterly, Vol.24, No.4 591-599
Waever, O. 1998 “The Sociology of a Not so International Discipline: American and European Developments in International Relations” in International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4
Waltz, K. 1979 Theory of International Politics, McGraw-Hill
Woyach, R. 1996 “International Relations Theory and the New World Order” Mershon International Review Vol.40

11.5.07

Constructivism



What are the contributions and limitations of a constructivist approach to IR?


The “old guard” of constructivism points back to Foucault in order to criticizes the watering down of constructivism in Wendt’s work. His acceptance of realist and liberal premises is frequent pointed to by his critiques when claiming that Wendt was not able to build a bridge between the two but in fact simply crossed the bridge to the other side. These defend that substantive (rationalist) theories and social (reflectivist) theories simply cannot come together.

Personally I believe he was successful in challenging the basic logical flaw of the traditional theories on what concerns the inherent anarchy of the international system which does not mean that a definite bridge between the two approaches was built. Showing how concepts in IR are social constructs and how state-centrism is historically a self-fulfilling prophecy was indeed achieved but a bridge only becomes a bridge once people start to use it. Constructivism is an expanding school in IR as so its body of work is still rather limited specially if one compares it to the dimension of the traditional schools. Wendt’s new bridge might have caused authors on both camps to re-evaluate their arguments and positioning in the field but it has not gathered the desirable momentum and autonomy. The question if it is viable depends on what Wendt is looking for at the end of the road. An autonomous school or a theoretical impact in the field, if viability implies an autonomous school he has failed, if alternatively viability is measured by impact then his middle ground has been instrumental in terms of stimulating change and debate. His positive take on IR is empowering and logically sound, particularly his take on the possibilities for change and his de-naturalization of self-help (actually an institution dependent on forms of interaction) and of anarchy as an intersubjective construction.

His writings are not yet seen as a school or a sub-school of its own as happened with Hedley Bull’s English school. Wendt remains a non-realist statist that joined the mainstream debate with softened constructivism. His belief in sovereign states as the dominant form of political actors in the international system and his insistence on science as the good criteria for sound scholarly work have ultimately put his bridge under attack from both sides of the camp.




Do you think Wendt’s goals of achieving middle ground between mainstream rational and reflectivist approaches is a viable one?



The “old guard” of constructivism points back to Foucault in order to criticizes the watering down of constructivism in Wendt’s work. His acceptance of realist and liberal premises is frequent pointed to by his critiques when claiming that Wendt was not able to build a bridge between the two but in fact simply crossed the bridge to the other side. These defend that substantive (rationalist) theories and social (reflectivist) theories simply cannot come together.

Personally I believe he was successful in challenging the basic logical flaw of the traditional theories on what concerns the inherent anarchy of the international system which does not mean that a definite bridge between the two approaches was built. Showing how concepts in IR are social constructs and how state-centrism is historically a self-fulfilling prophecy was indeed achieved but a bridge only becomes a bridge once people start to use it. Constructivism is an expanding school in IR as so its body of work is still rather limited specially if one compares it to the dimension of the traditional schools. Wendt’s new bridge might have caused authors on both camps to re-evaluate their arguments and positioning in the field but it has not gathered the desirable momentum and autonomy. The question if it is viable depends on what Wendt is looking for at the end of the road. An autonomous school or a theoretical impact in the field, if viability implies an autonomous school he has failed, if alternatively viability is measured by impact then his middle ground has been instrumental in terms of stimulating change and debate. His positive take on IR is empowering and logically sound, particularly his take on the possibilities for change and his de-naturalization of self-help (actually an institution dependent on forms of interaction) and of anarchy as an intersubjective construction.

His writings are not yet seen as a school or a sub-school of its own as happened with Hedley Bull’s English school. Wendt remains a non-realist statist that joined the mainstream debate with softened constructivism. His belief in sovereign states as the dominant form of political actors in the international system and his insistence on science as the good criteria for sound scholarly work have ultimately put his bridge under attack from both sides of the camp.


How convincing is the argument that “anarchy” is what states make of it?


In general lines Alexander Wendt lacks the parsimony of Neo-Realism but also does not distance itself from the possibility of exercising practical normative theory as is the case with radical post-modernists. Ultimately, Alexander Wendt does not consider behavioural-individualism and cognitive-constructivism as mutually exclusive. Originating from the constructivist school he followed Robert Keohane’s advice calling for constructivists to empirically test out their hypothesis in order to supposedly make their theory more scientifically sound and reliable. The result has been that the nature of interaction among states can be both product of the rational dynamics of a previously constructed system which is not static but can in fact be reviewed and overcome through processes of intersubjective interaction.

Wendt does not shy away from meta-theory, it shares with other positivist schools of Marxism, Neorealism and Neoliberalism the understanding the succession of historical processes as being cumulative and path-dependant. Wendt agrees with Waltz that the nature of the current international relations dynamics is anarchic but that this anarchy is circumstantially constructed. In practical terms, Wendt fundamentally disagrees with the traditional theories in the causes for the current state of international affairs in the relational trend but not in its actual existence. This means that, in theory, he will also propose distinct policy-making and notions about how state relations in international can and should change. Here is where problems can arise, when going about policy-making, being in a suppose middle ground is both a blessing and a curse. How to go on about the practicality of problem-solving on the everyday life of foreign-policy making by simultaneously using two grand schools of IR that are frequently not compatible is the big task ahead.

His argument is excellent in convincing readers that it is not the case that states are what anarchy makes of them. The opposite, however, might not always be true. Not all states have the leverage to define the nature of anarchy as they wish and this anarchy, because it is constantly being disputed, has so far had the tendency to constantly fall back into trap of the old game of power-politics.